Human Rights Dialogue (1994–2005): Series 2, No. 6 (Spring/Summer 2001): Rights and the Struggle for Health: Articles: Questioning Health and Human Rights

May 6, 2001

In the early 1990s the World Health Organization (WHO) decided that it wanted to eradicate tuberculosis. This would be no small task given the fact that multi-drug resistant TB (MDR-TB) was again gaining ground, primarily in Third World countries. In order to curb the spread of MDR-TB, many medical NGOs--including my own, Médecins Sans Frontières (MSF)--have become committed to WHO's program, which instructs that no patient should be treated unless you can expect an 80 percent rate of compliance from the population to which he or she belongs. If previous evaluations lead you to think that you are unlikely to reach this high rate of compliance, then it is better not to treat. The idea behind the program was that doctors should refrain from treating patients rather than risk spreading MDR-TB--which would lead to the deaths of many more people.

So in the name of this eradication program, in the cause of struggling against MDR-TB, for the sake of nice statistics, MSF and other humanitarian aid groups accepted that human beings, people of real flesh and blood, ought to be sacrificed. This is a moral and practical dilemma of a kind that medical practitioners and health professionals face all the time while working in the field. Who are we to decide who should live and who should die? For me, the terms of this dilemma ought to be posed in practical and political terms, rather than in terms of human rights. The issue of sacrifice is one that ought to be determined by the community, not by scientific experts, and the language of human rights is too vague to help in these determinations. Human rights claims often conflict with one another; no sooner has one been evoked that another, contradictory one emerges. This is because a list of human rights is not a consistent and coherent entity. Even worse, WHO's definition of a "right to health" is hopelessly ambiguous. I have never seen any real analysis of what is meant by the concept of "health" and "health for all," nor do I understand how anyone could seriously defend this notion. For WHO, health does not consist of the absence of disease or handicaps; it is the state of complete physical, mental, and social well being. It has nothing to do with concrete persons, concrete diseases, or concrete explanations about health.

Nor does this definition of a "right to health" help medical practitioners make decisions in difficult cases of when to treat and how to treat, as in the MDR-TB example. Guiding these decisions are two prominent, but very different, models. The first, which one might call the "public health model," stresses the promotion of overall public health standards. The second, which one might call the "humanitarian model," stresses the value of direct treatment of existing medical conditions. There is thus a conflict of values informing the decisions of health professionals--values of general, perfect public health standards versus values of direct treatment and direct help to persons in need of medical attention.

According to the public health model, the most important factors in decision-making should be how badly off the people affected by these conditions are in absolute and relative terms, how costly prevention or treatment would be, and how much patients would benefit from particular policies. This approach is oriented toward bringing about the best long-term health outcomes. If treatment is the best way to contribute to these long-term outcomes then one should treat, but if denying medical care to people who need it now is the best long-term strategy, then no treatment should be given. This model is generally accepted by WHO and clearly informs its policies regarding TB. Because TB patients need special follow-ups for at least eight to ten months, the public health threat is increased by so-called defaulters--a word that has moral overtones, and refers to those who abandon treatment prematurely. Defaulters threaten other members of the community because they might develop MDR-TB.

The humanitarian model asserts that our primary obligation is to give direct medical treatment to people who require medical attention. Essentially, we should try to treat as much as we can, regardless of what effects this may have in the future. It is the role of the medical practitioner to answer to patients' demands first, within the limits of his or her abilities. This implies that the practitioner must first seek to understand the always-complex interests of the particular patient he or she is examining. Until 1994 MSF applied this model by encouraging its medical teams to treat TB outside of the procedures promoted by WHO; increasing pressure from the international aid community has made this increasingly difficult. In 1994 MSF issued a new TB guideline that referred explicitly to WHO's declaration on the eradication TB as a public health priority. This guideline appeared without any internal debate--a fact that demonstrates that a "scientific" approach to the cost of human life imposed itself as evidence, not as a question. During the last two years, fortunately, things have been slowly changing.

The humanitarian model is preferable to the public health model on both moral and practical grounds. Medical practitioners should not be understood as the representatives of society or of its supposed interests towards patients, as the public health model requires. Instead, their role is to deal individually and sensitively with persons who are ill. Moreover, the public health model falsely presupposes the exactitude and validity of epidemiological predictions. I have a deep skepticism toward epidemiological prediction, insofar as it presumes that the future can be reduced to epidemiological patterns. Though epidemiology certainly has value, it is often used in a scientifically unsustainable way as a "proof" that certain policies will lead to certain outcomes. One simply needs to observe the number of correlations that are insidiously supposed to indicate causal relationships, and the manner that these supposed causal relationships are then translated into policy prescriptions, to understand the empirical and moral implausibility of this model. Statistical abstractions are falsely transformed into certainties, and some modes of treatment (such as the anti-TB treatment program that should have been pursued by MSF in Angola) are rendered taboo as a result.

Epidemiological "certainties" also create the illusion that obstacles to the treatment of disease are insurmountable, when often what is really lacking is a commitment on the part of politicians and the medical community. WHO, for instance, prefers to stick with the strategy of disease eradication, even if this means embracing a policy of human sacrifice, instead of recommending resumption in TB research. Yet TB is like any other infectious disease: It evolves genetic mutations that require new antibiotics. Nobody has bothered to raise this issue because TB patients are poor and do not provide a profitable market for drugs. The public health model simply assumes these political and economic conditions.

The public health model requires us to exchange corpses for would-be corpses. To me, that is a strange swap. It is morally and medically--and, I would say, humanly--unacceptable. Does taking a human rights, a "right to health," approach on the issue of MDR-TB help us adjudicate between the merits of the public health and the humanitarian model? I would say no.

A real issue, a practical one that might be defended from a human rights perspective, is the substitution of the right to health care for the right to health. I would like to see activism focus on the delivery of health care, since this can have concrete consequences for real human beings. Disease is an inalienable fact of life, but lack of access to appropriate medical care is not. Is this really a "human rights" issue? I'm not so sure. But it is at least a common concern that I think we can all agree upon.

You may also like

OCT 24, 2024 Article

Artificial Intelligence and Election Integrity in 2024

This final project from the first CEF cohort discusses the effects of AI on election integrity as billions of people go to the polls in 2024.

OCT 22, 2024 Video

Ethical Leadership in International Affairs

In this message for Global Ethics Day 2024, Carnegie Council President Joel Rosenthal shares his thoughts on ethical leadership and the role that ethics must play ...

OCT 16, 2024 Video

Empowering Next-Gen Civic Leaders

The keynote event for Global Ethics Day 2024 featured a panel discussion on how we might enhance youth participation and intergenerational collaboration in civic life.

Not translated

This content has not yet been translated into your language. You can request a translation by clicking the button below.

Request Translation